terça-feira, dezembro 17, 2002

Schoenberg and the Audience: Modernism, Music, and Politics in the Twentieth Century




LEON BOTSTEIN



I. Polemical Preliminaries


These festival weeks have had nothing to do with music. Schoenberg's followers have overdone it. What the consequence of the absolute domination by dodecaphony will be ... is that in ten years, I am convinced, no one will talk about the twelve-tone system.--G.F. Malipiero, June 1932
It seems that the last twenty years of eclecticism in contemporary music may have finally undone what "Schoenberg's followers" have "overdone" for nearly half a century. It is now respectable and even fashionable to concede that perhaps audiences have been right all along. Abstract, inaccessible, unfriendly, harsh, hard to follow, dense, even boring are still the adjectives applied by most concert-goers to Arnold Schoenberg's music. The twentieth-century composer, once most highly respected by generations of academics, whose music and theoretical writings reveal a daunting intellect and capacity for analysis, and whose own legendary contempt for others became routinized posthumously among those who specialized in his defense, now appears entirely vulnerable. With a slight edge of delight, critics are increasingly able to declare?along with Malipiero, and only superficially in imitation of Boulez, decades later?that Schoenberg is "dead."

Although thinking and writing about Schoenberg remain valued academic pursuits, to the public beyond academic circles Schoenberg, except for a few early works, commands little spontaneous affection, and at best a grudging respect. If his music is as great as he and his disciples claimed, why does it remain so difficult, so merely intellectual for so many; why after three quarters of a century are essays in the genre of Alban Berg's 1924 classic "Why is Schoenberg's Music so Difficult to Understand?" still appropriate?

Five basic factors currently stand in way of a sympathetic reconsideration of Schoenberg. First and foremost is the success of the so-called "post-modern." With the collapse of the perceived tyranny of those who viewed Schoenberg as the true prophet of new music, voices have emerged (some of them repentant former adherents to the cause) who actually relish the slaughter of the main sacred cow. From 1945 until the early 1980s, the accepted wisdom among composers and scholars echoed Ernst Krenek's closing comments at the Second International Schoenberg Conference in Vienna in 1984: Schoenberg and the Second Viennese School had altered musical thinking forever. No composer in the future would be able to circumvent Schoenberg and his influence, even if he was to write minimalist and tonal music. Just fifteen years later most successful younger contemporary composers appear to have paid little or no attention to Schoenberg. This has altered the paradigm of the history of twentieth century music that held sway into the mid-1970s, in which Schoenberg played the central role.

Second is the accumulated weight of sustained historical reevaluation. Those who question how modern Schoenberg really was challenge a facile equivalence between the terms "modernist" or "avant-garde" and the twentieth century. Perhaps, they seem to say, modernism in the sense of Schoenberg and his school refers merely to one limited historical period and group within the twentieth century. Or there is the line of argument first put forth decades ago independently by Pierre Boulez and Elliott Carter questioning how far Schoenberg had really traveled from a dependency on late nineteenth-century musical models. Were not Webern, Varèse, Ives, Messiaen, and even Stravinsky equally innovative and significant? This differentiation within modernism sought to help emancipate post-World War II composition from too exclusive a bias in favor of Schoenberg. A divergent view of the century and modernity emerges from these types of revisionism, one in which Schoenberg holds merely one place of prominence among many. Schoenberg may have been less a radical conservative and more a radical reactionary, one who carried Wagner's belief in a progressive imperative for music to an absurd extreme into an age in which history would no longer matter.

By refusing to see Schoenberg as the pivotal figure in the history of twentieth-century music, these revisionists create a third factor: they detach Schoenberg's music and its aesthetic and historical valuation from the social and political projects to which it was once inextricably linked. During the 1920s, Hanns Eisler, who retained an unqualified admiration for Schoenberg, his teacher, was among the first in Schoenberg's circle to speculate independently about the function of new music in modernity. Schoenberg's modernism consistently offended its audience. If that audience had been merely made up of smug owners of capital and their bourgeois apologists, there might have seemed something redeemingly "progressive" about Schoenberg's brand of modernism. But the failure of Schoenberg's modernism to gain any audience beyond its own elite of admirers?however constituted?revealed just how hollow were his supporters' appeals to historical necessity or a Platonic belief system that legislated a normative ideal of musical thought and form and therefore a typology of proper listening.

Since Schoenberg's brand of innovation as well as his Jewish identity became the focus of anti-Semitic right-wing politics early in the 1920s and later the object of Nazi persecution in the 1930s, the dissonances between the progressive in politics and the modernist in music were left unresolved. The alliance between the two went largely unquestioned for decades, even well after 1945. In the context of Cold War politics, Eisler's challenge to Schoenberg and his school from the left could be discredited as "Stalinist" and reactionary, while Schoenberg's brand of modernism continued, until the late 1960s, to appear as a non-subversive but forward-looking contemporary line of defense of individuality and freedom against uniformity and tyranny within the "free world."

Adorno's analysis of Schoenberg and his influence created a powerful critical and philosophical framework that buttressed Schoenberg's post-war influence, particularly in academic circles. According to this line of interpretation, modernism in music of the sort audible in Webern and in the work of the younger composers supported at Darmstadt and Donaueschingen in the 1950s and 1960s eloquently confronted the corrupting influences represented in the West by commercialism and mass society, the very ills that had helped fascism succeed.

With the receding prestige of socialist and progressive politics in the early 1980s, the growing critique of the liberal welfare state in England and America and ultimately the collapse of Communism and and fall of the Berlin Wall, the critique of capitalist culture and society put forward by Adorno and other Frankfurt School contemporaries, particularly Herbert Marcuse, became less attractive in the West to new generations of young people. Schoenberg and his notions of musical modernism were gradually detached from a plausible justifying political and historical logic locating them on the side of freedom and anti-fascism, and therefore of the angels.

While the later twentieth century heirs of the left have largely rejected modernism in favor of popular musical culture as an important dimension of political resistance, neo-conservatives have taken their own peculiar revenge on Schoenberg. Some have risen to Schoenberg's defense, citing his work and legacy as a bulwark against the collapse of cultural standards after the mid-1960s. Other neo-conservatives, however, have delighted in the idea that the largely liberal and leftwing post-war academic community's "emperor had no clothes" after all.

The fourth factor working against Schoenberg is the reemergence of an empirical and principled set of arguments prevalent at the turn of the century that defend tonality (or something very much like it) as natural and objective. According to this argument, which makes an appeal to normative philosophy, psychology, and physics, certain ways of organizing sound and time in music correspond to facts and laws of nature. In the early twentieth century, Schoenberg found himself on the side of those who argued against the idea that the Western system of harmony was privileged and rooted in nature, rendering tonality normative and objective. The sophisticated revival of the idea of a "natural" music has been fueled partly by linguistic theory (e.g. Chomsky and generative grammar), language philosophy (from the late Wittgenstein on) and the analysis of syntax.

Theorists as disparate in their approaches as Boretz and Epstein have suggested that when we look carefully at music as a reflexive system of communication we need to explain rather than dismiss the failure of any music to gain response, engage listeners or be easily preserved in memory. Perhaps it is not tonality that is natural. But the need for particularly evident patterns in music: repetition, focal points, continuities, tensions, resolutions and regularity?the accumulation of classes of events that can be processed and associated readily by the brain?may be universal. Schoenberg's modernism may lack these requirements because of an inherent conflict between the way we are as humans and the way twelve-tone music is organized. The wide dissemination (or to put it more plainly, the popularity) of a form of music need not be considered a sign of vulgarity, ignorance or concession to corrupt fashion or style. Populist politics and high theory have now merged: Schoenberg's brand of modernism, particularly in its twelve-tone phase, becomes a failed experiment that cannot intersect effectively with wider human experience cognitively and therefore either aesthetically or politically.

The fifth and final barrier to a sympathetic rehearing of Schoenberg today is ironically the difficulty we have in transcending the accumulated traditional rhetoric of criticism and defense surrounding the question of Schoenberg. Schoenberg and his disciples in the 1920s can be compared properly to the circle around the poet Stefan George, to whose work Schoenberg turned at a pivotal moment when the composer took a decisive step away from tonality. But the most apt comparison is with Richard Wagner. Not only did they both have disciples and demand uncommon degrees of loyalty from their followers, but Wagner and Schoenberg invented and institutionalized a rhetoric of self-defense and description. They both brilliantly placed themselves within music history and connected their work to past and future. Institutions designed to preserve and defend the Schoenberg legacy were created, first in Los Angeles, then in Vienna. Schools of composition and criticism that developed after 1945 relied heavily on Schoenberg's analysis of compositional methods, his views on form and structure, and his readings of Mozart and Brahms. To generations of Schoenberg admirers, followers and scholars, any departure from this self-constituted (or auto-poetic) code of discourse of defense and description was tantamount to ignorance or betrayal.

Schoenberg's philosophy of music and his logic of self-estimation have cast a decisive shadow over music theory and musicology in this century. Whether it is the concept of "idea" (as opposed to "style"), the "Grundgestalt," "developing variation," the "emancipation of the dissonance" or the relation of music and text, the way Schoenberg thought and wrote about music and its meaning has had perhaps more influence in the arenas of performance practice and critical approaches to music in this century than his own music has had on the writing of new music. At the end of this century, almost fifty years after Schoenberg's death, it is in part the institutionalized charisma of Schoenberg the teacher and theorist that retards a new appreciation of his music. Perhaps if we successfully challenge the rhetoric of Schoenberg and his most ardent posthumous defenders, we will be able to open up new avenues of access to his music.




II. Music and Psychology




TO MUSIC





Music: breath of statues. Perhaps:
stillness of paintings. You language where languages end. You time,
placed vertically on the course of hearts that expire.




Feelings ... for whom? O you the transformation
of feelings ... into what??: into audible landscape.
You stranger: music. You heartspace
grown out of us. Innermost thing of ours,
which, exceeding us, forces us out, ?
sacred farewell:
when the inner surrounds us
as the most practiced distance, as the other side
of the air:
pure,
like a giant,
no longer livable.
?R. M. Rilke, Munich, January 11-12, 1918



In 1926 the Polish composer Karol Szymanowski completed a draft of an essay on contemporary music. It was not published in his lifetime and appeared first in 1958 (see Appendix, p. 47). In it, Szymanowski argues that Schoenberg alone represents a true break with the past; Schoenberg was the only one to "cross the Rubicon" into modernity. Szymanowski understands Debussy, Stravinsky and Strauss as tied to pre-war traditions. At the same time Szymanowski remains entirely aware of the extent to which Schoenberg is not just a European but distinctly a German. He clearly identifies Schoenberg with a tradition of German composition and sees him as the heir to Wagner: the composer who represents the future of German music. Szymanowski echoes Berg's 1924 conclusion that Schoenberg would "predominate in German music for the next fifty years." Yet Szymanowski accepts the universal consequences of Schoenberg's achievement. He is unstinting in his praise and admiration for Schoenberg's philosophical vocabulary and rhetoric of self-assessment. The essay is curious in part because Szymanowski?unlike Stravinsky and Copland later on in the 1960s?never sought to emulate Schoenberg in his own approach to composition by experimenting with twelve-tone composition.

What struck Szymanowski was Schoenberg's remarkable sojourn from Wagnerism to a new modernism. No other composer had worked so well in the pre-World War I expressionist idiom and yet had shown the courage to break away. The decisive step was the explicit severing of a long tradition of parallelism between musical form and structure and "direct psychological truth." Schoenberg put forward a notion of absolute music that cut against the traditions of emotional response and attachment to music so eloquently witnessed by Rilke's 1918 poem. Yet Szymanowski remained ambivalent about this. On the one hand, the "natural" development of music required that music somehow become finally independent, in the twentieth century, of reality and life, and reverse the exaggerated emotionalism of romanticism. Szymanowski shared a Hanslick-like prejudice about the inherently "absolute" non-representational character of music. On the other hand, he realized the power of an historical achievement, beginning in the nineteenth century and culminating with expressionism, in which the "horizontal" dimension of music became gradually influenced by the vertical, creating an "enriched" sound world which, metaphorically speaking, ran parallel with the "lyrics of direct life reality." Music became "rooted in life's psychological rhythm," just as Rilke suggests in his response to hearing music. Extended tonality and extreme chromaticism, strengthened by the expanded palette of orchestral sound, made the Rilke-like parallelism between feeling and sound irresistable.

Schoenberg brought this historical process to completion and ultimately abandoned the residual framework of the "horizontal"; the "vertical" dimension of music was placed in the foreground. He rendered the "vertical" in music absolute. Gone were issues of "mood" and "color" or even the contrast between the static and the dynamic highlighted by modulation. The "absolute vertical" found a value in itself, not as a function of musical "expression." This led to "the essential atomism" of Schoenberg's modernism, by which Szymanowski means the twelve-tone compositional breakthrough of the 1920s. Szymanowski's essay ends abruptly, incomplete, with praise for Schoenberg's ethical authenticity and seriousness as well as a reference to the consequences of the opening up of a "limitless domain" in which truth became subjective and relative. Schoenberg had created a space in which everything seemed now permissible.

Crucial to the contemporary and posthumous defense of Schoenberg and the modernist tradition linked to his innovations from the 1920s has been an explicit and implicit assent to his critique of the traditions and character of how audiences listened, followed and understood music. An audience that was truly musically literate, which thought purely musically i.e. could grasp music without any refuge in psychological allegory, either of narrative or mood?such an audience could truly appreciate the music of Schoenberg and his followers. As Schoenberg himself pointed out, his greatest success as a composer derived from his capacity, in his pre-twelve-tone music, to facilitate with great originality and inventiveness the listener's capacity to listen allegorically and through the use of allusion, without refuge in illustration or representation. Furthermore, as Szymanowski observed, the extension of tonality and the virtuosity in the use of modulation displayed by Schoenberg in Gurrelieder, for example, expanded the utility of music as a framework?independent of the text?for internal psychological reflection on the part of the listener. But then Schoenberg stopped himself and history short, interrupting the continuity of these traditions. (A typical pictorial representation of the sort of listening common at the end of the nineteenth century is the 1895 painting by the English painter Francis Dicksee [1853-1928], entitled A Reverie, reproduced in figure 1.)

One can locate the cause for the widespread contemporary and posthumous perception that Schoenberg was the creator of a unique radical modernism in precisely this interruption, the self-conscious break with the parallelism between music and life (and therefore language) as expressed in the expectations of generations of European composers and audiences. By creating a new mode of pitch relationship and therefore a new basis for constructing the basic cells or thematic elements for works of music, Schoenberg in the 1920s explicitly attacked the dominant habit of listening within nineteenth-century musical culture, rendering it irrelevant and useless. With the fundamental abandonment of tonality, music lost its connection to the Rilke-like internal psychological dialogue conducted by the individual and therefore, as Szymanowski suggests, its evident connection to life. The aesthetic dimension had been emancipated from the psychologically instrumental. But the question remained: into what and for what?

It is well to remember that many of Schoenberg's earliest and most ardent defenders and advocates were young listeners who sought a new and different inspiration from music; they were not professional musicians or critics. Consider for example the fascinating fragment by Arnold Zweig from 1913 entitled "A Quartet Movement by Schoenberg." In this short prose work Schoenberg emerges as the prophetic and triumphant outsider who has arrived to rescue Europe through art exactly one hundred years after Napoleon's defeat at the battle of Leipzig in 1813. The story takes place in 1913. An Eastern European Jew is on his way to Palestine. After travelling through Berlin he visits his brother in Leipzig The young man, the protagonist, is both impressed and revolted by the middle-class opulence and self-satisfaction evident in the architecture and the people he encounters in Leipzig. In Leipzig the sound of the Saxon dialect reminds him of the French and of Napoleon. The reunion with his brother is unsatisfactory. He becomes bored.

He wanders into a concert without seeing what is on the program. It is a quartet concert. The first work is by Haydn and the young man is lost in a quite typical reverie. He dreams of nature and the simple pleasures of life. A pre-modern idyllic world appears before his eyes. After enthusiastic applause the quartet plays the next work. The audience is stunned; it does not know how to react. But the young man is transported. He is inspired: he senses through the music the power of modernity, the city, and of science and progress. He also senses the alienation of the modern individual. He perceives the extent to which an excessive optimism about modernity prevalent within the audience has gone awry. A nameless artist, the composer of this new music, reveals through sounds the contradictions of modernity and truthfully celebrates the possibilities of cultural renewal. Aesthetic innovation and ethical truth merge in the music.

Although the audience is at a loss, the young man leaves the concert hall suddenly seized by doubt about his own plans to leave Europe for the more primitive and yet-to-be-realized new social order of Palestine. As he wanders about on his way to the train station to resume his journey, he sees a poster and notices the name of the composer whose music he has just heard: Arnold Schoenberg, a fellow Jew. Although he proceeds with his plans, he senses that he must ultimately return to Europe to take on the cause of the rebirth of European culture along the path set forth by Schoenberg. Schoenberg's music has awakened the young man to the idea that he has not exhausted his identity as a European. A sense of homelessness, triggered by the pogroms in the East he is fleeing, has been assuaged by the music. The possibilities for a cultural and political future, for internal personal are rekindled, forcing him to reconsider his Zionism, his life's plan and his sense of self. The story ends with the hero repeating the words "O return, o return."

It is more than likely that the music Zweig had in mind was either Schoenberg's Op. 7 or Op. 10, both of which were performed in Berlin in 1912 and 1913, the year the fragment was written. Zweig therefore implicitly refers to at least two works which created a great uproar in Schoenberg's career and helped established his reputation as a radical. (At issue, therefore, is not Verklärte Nacht or Gurrelieder.) Although the music Zweig alludes to is not the same repertoire Szymanowski discusses, Schoenberg's break with the past was well underway in Opp. 9 and 10. Op. 7, however, possessed a "very definite but private program." Nevertheless, Szymanowski's 1926 construct of Schoenberg's project can be applied to Op. 7, Op. 9, and Op. 10. Despite the presence of poetic texts, Schoenberg's first decisive breaks with habits of listening based on psychological parallelism between musical space and time and real life sensibilities, particularly the internal clock of reflection, took place before the invention of twelve-tone composition, particularly in Op. 9.

Zweig's account is all the more remarkable for its political overtones. Indeed, as the story develops Schoenberg functions for the young man as modernity's Napoleon: the new-world historical hero from humble origins. Napoleon was a hero to most Jews because of his role in their emancipation. The image of the Jewish composer as a new Napoleon redeeming the possibilities of European culture in the name of freedom, ethical progress, and enlightened modernity, fits quite closely to Schoenberg's own self-assessment before his stunning and disillusioning encounter with anti-Semitism in the 1920s. Zweig and Schoenberg also implicitly agree in their critique of the pre-World War I audience. Zweig gives us a picture of an uncomprehending group of affluent middle-class Europeans, suffused with culture, who delighted only in the familiar. There is however no description of booing or hissing, as took place in Vienna. Zweig's account of his fellow audience members is critical but not entirely dismissive (the experience after all raises his hopes about the use of art as an instrument of cultural and social renewal). One comes away from the fragment with a sense that confronting the public with a radical new art may in fact set in motion a social and political transformation.

Leaving aside the many implications imbedded in Zweig's strange story, it is curious that Zweig's protagonist's habit of listening did not change with the music. He listened to Schoenberg the way he listened to Haydn. Indeed, one way to understand what was going on in concert halls between the years 1909 and 1913 at performances of Schoenberg's music?events that attracted furious response and intensive critical attention?is to concentrate on one consistent thread within the notion of psychological listening shared by Zweig's protagonist, his audience, and one which is implicit in Szymanowski's analysis: the act of listening with the visual imagination. Rilke confirms the pervasive attachment to music as inspiring of a species of sight; music is the breathing statue, the stillness of paintings, the audible landscape.

The visual imagery inspired by the idea of music at the turn of the century, particularly in light of Schoenberg's own brief career as a painter and his life-long engagement with the connection between the musical and the visual, merits close historical scrutiny. What changes in Zweig's story is the substance and character of that which is visualized or imagined through music. It is in turn the perceived failure of this mode of listening to music that drove Schoenberg, after World War I, to the complete break with expressionism, a break whose courage so impressed Szymanowski.







AVANT-GARDE THEATRE



?Avant-garde? has become a rubbery term which is applied to art that is considered to be anti-traditional or new. At its most basic level, it is a descriptive term for what is new at any given time. That is, any new artistic direction. Avant-garde art is characterised by a radical political posture. It is also hostile to other artistic formats. In many ways, it is easier to define the avant-garde by what it is against. All the different varieties of avant-garde reject oppressive social structures, condemn conventional artistic forms and are antagonistic towards the public. The avant-garde is essentially a philosophical grouping. Artists working in this area are linked by common views of the Western social order as well as a particular aesthetic approach. The term ?avant-garde? is a military term for the front section of an army which prepares the way for the troops. The literary sense of the word came into usage at the end of the nineteenth century. There is no single ?avante-garde? theatre. We can, however, note certain characteristics which may denote the avant-garde. "The essence of avant-gardism is that it is never satisfied with accepted standards and is constantly searching" (Pronko 3).

Early avant-garde artists were primarily concerned with creating a revolution in society. Alfred Jarry, with his Ubu trilogy, is often considered to be the founder of the avant-garde. It is a play which reflects the anarchy of Jarry?s revolt against society and the artistic ?rules? of realism and naturalism. Cabaret provided a nurturing environment for many avant-garde artists.




--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

CABARET
Cabaret was the product of changes in urban life and artistic taste at the start of the twentieth century. "The disruptions of big-city life encouraged the creation of forms of art and entertainment that were likewise heterogeneous and fragmented" (Jelavich 10). The variety show was the most popular of these new diversions and cabaret copied this format but the artists sought to give it a "higher" literary and artistic content.

Today when we speak of Cabaret, images of sleazy nightclubs operating as strip joints, dimly lit back alleys and smoke filled corners are often conjured up. These versions of cabaret are distant relatives of the literary cabaret which began in late nineteenth century France and evolved into a vehicle for the political and cultural satire of the German Kabarett of the 1920s and 1930s. "They share with the artistic cabaret only the presence of spectacle and an intimate space in which people can smoke and talk, eat and drink (Appignanesi 9).

Cabaret began to function as a laboratory for young artists to exchange ideas and opinions as well as providing the opportunity to hold a critical mirror up to topical events, morals, politics and culture. By positioning itself somewhere between the stage proper and variety, cabaret established its own defined performance space. "A flexible medium - with its impromptu stage, setting and programme - it shifted its focus with the times, without ever on the whole losing its rebellious wit or dissident, innovative nature" (Appignanesi 10). Therefore it is difficult to say what content went into a "typical" cabaret. A Cabaret could have included about 15 essentially unrelated series of acts including song, sketches, dance, monologue and poetry. This format is challenged by some programs which privilege one form over another (eg 1 hour play in the midst of unrelated material). The structural elements of cabaret may provide one way of defining the artform as a distinct style despite these contradictions:

small stage
smallish audience
an ambience of talk and smoke
audience-performer relationship is one of intimacy and hostility.
The cabaret performer plays directly to the audience. The actor never vanishes into the role (like Brecht, the actor is ever present).

Variations in the mode of Cabaret are enormous so today I?ll only identify some of the major manifestations of the art form.

The birthplace of Cabaret is unquestionably Paris in 1881. The first cabaret performers created an eclectic performing cat who could sing, dance, recite, write music and lyrics and entertain. The cat became a symbol of grace and magic and its prey was always the silly bourgeois society.

The movement emanated from a Parisienne club called the Chat Noir in Montmartre. The founder of this first artistic cabaret was the poet and painter, Rodolphe Salis. An initial feature of this new genre was to introduce satire into the cult of naturalism. "To shock the middle-class spectator into a realization that his respectable values were merely a thin veneer hiding a lust for the sewer which he had himself partially helped to create" (Appignanesi 16).

Montmatre was known to be the haunt of social outcasts: criminals, prostitutes, poor workers (both unemployed and employed). The choice of location has helped to ink the outcasts with the literary and artistic bohemia. Initially, poets, composers, writers, and painters gathered to chat and read each other?s work. They started serving drinks to those participating. Early programs offered at the Chat Noir were unstructured, involved improvisational spontaneity designed to shock and surprise. Participants include: Emile Goudeau (novelist) and Claude Debussy (composer). When representatives of the Paris establishment went to the Cabaret, they knew they were going to be insulted. The songs and poems were designed to parody middle-brow culture.

The Chat Noir artists lived like the people in Montmatre. Their works reflected the lives of the people. They used their speech rhythms and forms in an attempt to raise popular culture into an art which would ultimately influence mainstream literature.

Due to its expanded audience and a series of violent attacks on their elite audience, the Chat Noir was forced to move to the rue Victor Massé where it was to become the "focal point of the Paris night life and avant-garde" (Appignanesi 20). The performers were daring and directly insulted/attacked specific members of the elite while they were in the audience. One of the roles of cabaret was to be an artistic laboratory, "a revitalizing ground for tired artistic formulas" (Appignanesi 24). Alphonse Allais was a prominent figure at the Chat Noir. He was a consummate absurdist in his performances of monologues, sketches and story-telling. From the most mundane situation/idea "he would logically deduce the looniest, most macabre, and most unexpected of results" (Appignanesi 24).

The Chat Noir closed in 1897, but by this time, Montmartre was the artistic centre of Paris. (Chatnoiresque had become a current adjective of the period. It entered the argot dictionary to describe all events blending fantasy, and humour with a degree of impudence).

Other Cabarets formed around Montmatre including La Lune Rousse, Les Pantins, and most significantly, Le Mirliton. This last Cabaret was the home of Aristide Bruant whose work with street poetry and socio-critical songs meant that these became fundamental to the cabaret repertoire. One of the few women working in Cabaret at this time was Yvette Guilbert. She sang many of Bruant?s songs. Cabaret had to travel to Germany before women became an integral part of its makeup.



Cabaret in Paris at the turn of Century:

"The cabaret was a natural environment for the avant-garde. Spectacle was of its essence, and the avant-garde needed to make a spectacle of itself in order to be heard" (Appignanesi 64). The nature of cabaret program, that is, its discontinuity supplemented by ironical commentary reflected the basic composition of the experimental work of the time. "This kinship of cabaret and the early twentieth-century avant-garde was a two-way dynamic: one created the other and was in turn influenced by it" (Appignanesi 64).

The painters and writers who flocked to the cheap living quarters of Montmartre at the turn of the century extended the definition of artist so that it included lifestyle. That is, their pranks, banquets, festivities had the same imaginative source as their poems and paintings.

Fraudulence of avant-garde was tested by Lolo the donkey under the pseudonym of Joachim Raphael Boronalis.



CABARET IN GERMANY: 1900-1914:

Less free-spirited environment under Kaiser Wilhelm. Censorship, especially of drama, was strict and rigid sexual morality prevailed. Contributing factors to German cabaret:

1. Gossip of bohemian ambience of Montmartre and birth of Cabaret. Germany, however, lost some of the playful tone of the French original, and cabaret here takes on a more serious and satirical aggressive role.

2. Another starting point was Otto Julius Bierbaum?s 1900 attempt to raise the status of poplar variety show to serious art.

Ernst con Wolzogen (aristocrat and poet) opened Überbrettl? [brettl? is a term for the popular stage, while über added the meaning to ennoble/transcend the popular stage] In a theatre seating 650, Wolzogen attempted to create the mixture of satire, eroticism and lyricism which French Caberet originated. The size of the theatre made intimacy impossible while censorship softened the satirical edge of the work. The opening night program comprised:

PART A:

a part of Arthur Schnitzler?s Anatol cycle
pantomime Pierrot play
shadow play by Liliencron
subtle lyricist
mixture of poems and chansons performed by both women and men.
PART B:

parody by Christian Morgenstern (famous for his ?nonsense? verse/important German avant-garde poet), of d?Annunzio.
Bierbaum?s operetta-play, The Merry Husband.
This became the toast of the season
Although not strictly cabaret, it opened the door for smaller ventures to set up around it, including Max Reinhardt?s 1901 one-off performance of one-act parodies interspersed with commentaries on monarchy, songs and poems. So successful they decided to continue a program of literary parody. They were strictly censored a few times. This group became the Kleine Theatre which can be considered to be one of Germany?s first experimental theatres.

Berlin also used Cabaret as a meeting place and locale for performance, providing a bistro atmosphere. Max Tilke?s Der Hungrige Pegasus (The Hungry Pegusus) was a direct copy of the French Cabaret. Once a week, poets, writers and painters gather to smoke, talk and perform samples of their work. The laws were so strict that these performances were always the subject of police suspicion. Hans Hyan?s songs about the plight of the unemployed and adverse social conditions were extremely courageous.

Munich was a thriving art centre before World War I. It was famous for its bars and cafés which were the focal point for Bohemian artist, poets, actors and writers. Two key personalities were Emmy Hennings and Hugo Ball (married). Munich?s Simplicissimus cafe was often referred to as one of the ?intimate theatres? and was the venue for all kinds of eccentricities. Frank Wedekind was notorious for his ability to provoke, especially with respect to sexual topics. He was frequently called a libertine, an anti-bourgeois exploiter of sexuality and a threat to public morality. He would perform cabaret whenever his full-length plays were thwarted by censorship. His performances bordered on the obscene yet were extremely popular within Munich?s artistic community. His censorship trials hurled him into prominence (and prison). "Wedekind?s performances revelled in the licence given the artist to be a mad outsider, exempt from society?s normal behaviour" (Goldberg 35). Little of his work was performed without a scandal.

This pre-war development of Cabaret lead to a special style of performance which became known as DADA.

segunda-feira, dezembro 16, 2002

Tradutor automático:


(parece propaganda de curso de inglês!)



Arnold Schoenberg

(1874-1951), compositor Austrian-carregado, criador do sistema do doze-tom da composição musical, e um dos compositores os mais influential do 20o século.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

Fundo
O choenberg de S foi carregado setembro em 13, 1874, a uma família jewish em Viena. Ensinou-se que a composição, com ajuda no counterpoint do compositor austrian Alexander Zemlinsky, e em 1899 produziu seu primeiro trabalho principal, o poema Verklärte Nacht do tom (noite de Transfigured) para o sextet da corda. Em 1901 casou a irmã Mathilde de Zemlinsky, com quem teve duas crianças. Os pares moveram-se para Berlim, onde por dois anos Schoenberg ganhou uma vida por operettas orchestrating e dirigir um orchestra do cabaré.

Carreira em Viena, em Berlim, e nos estados unidos
I n Schoenberg 1903 retornaram a Viena para ensinar. Lá encontrou-se com seus estudantes mais bem sucedidos, os compositores austrian Anton Webern e Alban Berg, que se transformaram his amigos próximos. Em suas composições, Schoenberg empregou harmonias far-reaching, um traço que se tornasse mais tarde o atonality. Por causa deste, os motins erupted em ambos os premieres de seus primeiros dois quartets da corda em 1905 e em 1908. Tais experiências conduziram-lhe frequentemente à sensação persecuted por um público que não poderia compreender sua música.

Schoenberg também começou a pintura durante estes anos e exibiu seu trabalho com um grupo dos artistas no círculo do pintor russian Wassily Kandinsky. Este período foi marcado pela tragédia quando Mathilde teve um caso com seu professor da pintura, que cometeu o suicide depois que retornou a Schoenberg. Em 1911, o ano em que Schoenberg publicou sua teoria do livro da harmonia , aceitou uma posição ensinar em Berlim. Lá compôs um de seus trabalhos mais influential, Pierrot Lunaire (1912). Retornou a Viena em 1915. Os interruptions ocasionados pela guerra de mundo I, combinada com a busca de Schoenberg para que uma maneira assegure a lógica e a unidade na música do atonal, impediram que produza muitos trabalhos entre 1914 e 1923. Por 1923, entretanto, tinha terminado o formulation de seu método do doze-tom da composição. Morte de Mathilde que o mesmo ano era um sopro sério a Schoenberg, mas em 1924 encontrou-se com e casou-se Gertrud Kolisch, irmã de um violinist austrian. Com o invitation em 1925 ensinar a composição no academy das artes em Berlim, Schoenberg obteve finalmente uma posição prestigiosa, uma segurança financeira, e uma vida de família estável. Em 1932, o ano onde a filha do par foi carregada, ele terminou o segundo ato de seu und Aron de Moses da ópera (produzido posthumously, 1957).

O choenberg de S e sua família fujiram Nazi Germany a Paris em 1933. Em 1934 immigrated aos estados unidos, e aceitou uma posição ensinar em Boston. O ano seguinte, por causa de sua saúde, moveram-se para Los Angeles, onde seus dois filhos mais novos foram carregados. Após um ano como um lecturer na universidade de Califórnia do sul (1935), ensinou na universidade de Califórnia em Los Angeles de 1936 a 1944. Transformou-se um cidadão de ESTADOS UNIDOS em 1941. Schoenberg caiu seriamente doente em 1946, e em um ponto seu coração parou de bater; esta experiência é refletida em sua corda Trio (1946), escrito após sua recuperação. Na aposentadoria continuou a ensinar e compôr. Morreu julho em 13, 1951, em Los Angeles.

Evolução Musical
O estilo musical dos choenberg de S progrediu do romanticism 19th-century atrasado à técnica do doze-tom. Seus trabalhos adiantados do tonal são reminiscent da música do compositor alemão Johannes Brahms, mas antes por muito tempo do assimilated o chromaticism do compositor alemão Richard Wagner. Nos trabalhos tais como Verklärte Nacht Schoenberg conseguiu a intensidade do sentimento com as harmonias ricas e as melodias soaring longas suportadas por uma textura contrapuntal densa de motriz curtos, constantemente variando. Começando aproximadamente 1907 estes traços tornaram-se mesmo mais pronunciados em seus trabalhos do expressionist, em que o tonality foi abandonado e o formulário musical se tornou comprimido. O exemplo principal deste período é Pierrot Lunaire ; neste ajuste do verso macabre, o ensemble acompanhando da câmara emprega uma combinação diferente dos instrumentos para cada uma das 21 canções poema-baseadas do ciclo, e o soloist vocal usa o Sprechstimme (alemão para do "a voz discurso"), ou Sprechgesang (do" canção discurso"), uma mistura do discurso e a canção.

Um bout Schoenberg 1920 começou a formular sua técnica do doze-tom e a extrai-la em formulários musicais classical para estruturar suas composições. Todos seus estilos, entretanto, são destilados em sua realização mais maciça, und Aron de Moses . Schoenberg retornou ocasionalmente à composição do tonal, mas na maioria seus trabalhos dos de os 1930s e '40s onde tentou synthesize a técnica do doze-tom com os princípios formais tinha empregado durante seu período do expressionist. Esta síntese pode ser ouvida em seu piano Concerto do um-movimento (1942) e no trio monumental da corda.

O hrough Schoenberg e seus estudantes de T, o método do doze-tom transformou-se uma força dominando na composição do século de mid-20th e exerceu-se uma influência profunda no curso da música ocidental.

Jerry L. McBride, Arquivista (1981-86), Instituto De Arnold Schoenberg
Parte traseira

Copyright Microsoft do texto, 1993-1995. Usado com permissão.